|
In
Stoic philosophy at the time of Augustus, the meanings of human events
were believed to be discernible through knowledge of the rules that
governed nature and the cosmos. "Because [the rational spirit]
was present in all creatures," Ogilvie writes "there was a
common understanding between the different parts of the universe which
caused one event to be reflected in another. Hence there was nothing
implausible about supposing 'that the divine providence could be reproduced
in a sheep's liver or the flight of birds.'"(20) Entrails, in particular,
were an important resource to haruspices who sought to divine
the state of the cosmos.
"The liver was such a vital organ and was,
in stoic theory, a microcosm of the working of the universe, it
was believed that detailed examination could see in it a more intricate
pattern of what the gods intended [...]. The practice of divination
from the liver was patently defended by the philosopher Epictetus.
It remained one of the principal forms of augury."(21)
Divisions of the liver corresponded to
divisions of the heavens, and all related to cosmic and terrestrial
order.(22)
[page
65] A navigation through philosophical accounts of other
writers at the time of Seneca also yields a network of statements that
indicate the presence and legitimacy of divination practices in the
Roman Republic and Empire. Marcus Tullius Cicero's The Nature of
the Gods (which predates Seneca's work by a half-century) contains
a dialogue between Cotta, Velleius, Lucilius, and Balbus on matters
concerning religion and the deities.(23) While it should not be treated
as an unproblematic window into Seneca's thought, Cicero's text does
include Stoic discourse in the voice of Balbus. This is particularly
the case in the four characters' discussion of divination, which Cotta
designates as one of the two categories of religion.(24) Whereas Velleius
maintains that Epicurus has rid Romans of such superstition,(25) Balbus,
argues that the gods created and gave birds and other animals to humans
for the purpose of omens and signs of things to come. They are meant
for man and only man can unlock the significance of the signs. The gift
of prophecy is the best example of "proof that divine providence
concerns itself with the welfare of man."(26) Cotta, held to be
the closest in sentiment to Cicero himself, answers Balbus directly:
And what was the origin of your art of divination?
Who discovered the significance of a cleft in an animal's liver or
interpreted the raven's cry? Or the way the lots fall? Not that I
do not believe in these things [...]. But how omens came to be understood
is something I must learn from the philosophers [...]. But, you argue,
doctors too are often wrong. There is however to my mind no [page
66] comparison between medicine, which applies reasoning
which I can understand and the power of divination, the origin of
which is a mystery to me.(27)
Though Cotta will not directly reject
divination as a sign of the existence of the gods, he will not subscribe
to it until he determines its origins.(28) Furthermore, Cicero argues
that human error will always remain a factor in divination, so the practice
may only be as reliable as medical diagnoses, or (elsewhere) nautical
predictions.
The
stoic position as put forth by Balbus in Cicero's dialogue, then, is
that divination is the means by which humans may interpret the signs
given to them by the gods. This is then undercut by Cotta's emphasis
on human error and ultimate unreliability of the interpretation of signs
from the gods. Cicero cites a somewhat different Stoic viewpoint on
divination by entrails, however, in book I, chapter lii, of his
de divinatione: "The Stoics will not allow that the Deity
can be interested in each cleft in entrails, or in the chirping of birds.
They affirm that such interference is altogether indecorous, unworthy
of the majesty of the gods and an incredible impossibility."(29)
Here Cicero's text conflicts with both Balbus' words, and Ogilvie's
assertion that Stoics held divination of entrails in high regard. Whereas
Ogilvie states that the Stoics believed the liver could be examined
as a microcosm of the universe, the statement in Cicero denies that
entrails merit the notice of the gods.
Despite
disparate accounts on the Stoic's regard for animal entrails and their
relative adequacy as receptacles for divine messages, the presence of
statements on this facet of divination in the writings of Cicero and
others indicates that the practice was a prominent part of Roman religion.
Furthermore, there is a suggestion in the opening of Cicero's de
devinatione that the author holds Roman divination practices to
be more rational and advanced than that of [page
67] the Greeks. Cicero contrasts the etymology of the Roman
word for the practice, stemming from Divis, having to do with
gods, while the Greek word comes form the word for madness. He separates
divination as ritualistic art and divination by mere observation of
nature or visions. The former, he writes, is more reliable, as it is
based on observation and reason. The latter is more concerned with frenzy
and dreams. Perceived in this light, it is possible to suggest that
Seneca's selection of divination practices for dramatic treatment in
Oedipus exemplified the Roman improvement of Greek practices.
In other words, Seneca was one-upping the Greeks by making Tiresias
a rational, observant augur, rather than a frenzied prophet who gets
his answers from birds.
However, as far as Seneca's own views on the matter of divination by
entrails, the author is reticent in all writings but his tragedies.
As a Stoic philosopher, Seneca may have located the order of animals'
livers and entrails within the correspondent levels of the cosmos as
outlined in a general Stoic cosmology. Such a general cosmology, though,
cannot be taken for granted, given the range of interpretations of the
Stoic position, even within the writings of a single author like Cicero.
While
Seneca's views on divination specifically by the examination of animal
entrails are not to be found, the author does consider divination by
natural phenomenon in his Naturales quaestiones:
We differ from the Etruscans [...] in that we
believe that only certain things that happen regularly, ratione,
allow us to make the predictions of the future that come under the
head of divination [...]. [However] we just do not know enough about
the incidence of lightning and about birds' calls to make truly
verifiable inferences from them. With greater knowledge, more links
in the chain can be discoverable.(30)
According to Thomas G. Rosenmeyer, Stoics
in first century Rome believed errors in divination were due to the
misinterpretation of signs, rather than their unreliability. Seneca's
reluctance to place total trust in divination suggests a suspicion of
humanity's ability to read the future by [page
68] examination of natural phenomena.(31) If the account
of the divination ritual in Oedipus was informed by the notion
of human fallibility, perhaps Seneca was foregrounding error or unreliability
in the scene. Tiresias' blindness and necessary intervention by Manto
add further degrees of separation from a divine message in its unmediated
form. Thus, Tiresias is denied access to the identity of Laius' killer
not because the signs are inadequate, but because the prophet lacks
the necessary facilities to interpret them. Therefore, the scene functions
structurally within a narrative of the unraveling of a mysterygiving
clues, but not revealing the solution. As philosophical or religious
commentary, Seneca may have been registering his own sentiments concerning
divination by entrails, possibly vis-à-vis those of Cicero.
The practice is legitimate in discerning information or the will of
the gods, but may only be trusted as far as human ability.
One
may argue that the description of the disordered entrails of the bull
and heifer in Act II is only one of many gruesome scenes in Oedipus,
which similarly seem at first glance to exist solely for shock value.
For example, there is Creon's account of the oracle in the grove scene
in which a ghastly Laius, still bleeding from his wounds rises to condemn
his son. Jocasta commits suicide on stage by stabbing herself in the
womb in revulsion for giving birth to her own "grandchildren."
Oedipus, after blinding himself, continues to claw at the empty sockets,
tearing away "the last remaining shreds/Left of the raggedly uprooted
eyes."(32) Why, then, does the divination scene merit separate
analysis from the other the bloody sequences? My argument does not concern
whether Seneca had a "fascination" with the macabre or the
grotesque. What I hope to have shown is that dismissal of such scenes
as mere horror, or naïve treatment of what was later to receive
fullest enunciation in Shakespeare, is not a responsible scholarly act.
Neither the trajectory of evolution toward Shakespeare nor degeneration
of the Greeks do Seneca's work justice. Each makes the Roman text speak
with a twentieth century sensitivity and nostalgiaeither for the
more perfect Greek model, or for the catalyst that prompted Shakespeare's
emergence after a dry spell in the history of dramatic literature. By
relegating Oedipus and the other Senecan tragedies to these categories,
they are left to function only as a link in a chain of degeneration
or primitive origin. I propose, instead, a reexamination of these [page
69] scenes, through continual resituation within the context
of Seneca's world and society, which was inseparably wrapped up in the
religion of the time.
The divination scene in Act II of Oedipus is a moment that voices
the language of intelligibility of first-century Rome. By appropriating
the Greek myth and inserting a scene concerning Roman divination practices,
Seneca engaged in a strategy to stabilize a belief system. The scene
indicates to what extent divination was a very real way to show that
the order in the cosmos was in flux and could be measured by practitioners
like Tiresias and Manto in order to maintain stability. Furthermore,
as philosopher, Seneca turns a critical eye upon the particular divination
practices in circulation at the time of his dramatic activity. In Oedipus,
he examines the role of Tiresias as haruspex, and tempers the
position that divination was a legitimate means for understanding the
cosmos with a cautionary element of human fallibility and weakness.
The inability of Tiresias and Manto to discern the identity of Laius'
killer is not evidence for the scene's lack of contribution to the development
of the plot. Rather, the scene's inclusion posits that the disorder
of nature was directly proportionate to the disorder in the moral laws
and stability of the people, especially kings. In the face of such profound
disarray, the characters determine that the cosmic order had been upset
by something far worse than the killing of the king. It would appear,
then, that the divination scene is about more than mere spectacle. It
therefore merits more historiographically responsible treatment than
relegation to comparative analysis with Greek or Elizabethan tragedy.
Oedipus and Seneca, both, deserve another look.
Endnotes
-
Seneca: The Tragedies in Two
Volumes, ed. David R. Slavitt, (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins U. Press,
1995).
-
See T.S. Eliot, "Introduction," Seneca: His Tenne Tragedies Translated into English, ed. Thomas
Newton (Constable, 1927).
-
Clarence Mendell, Our Seneca
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1941) 200. See also J.W. Cunliffe,
The Influence of Seneca on Elizabethan Tragedy (London: Macmillan, 1893).
-
Moses Hadas, The Stoic Philosophy
of Seneca (Garden City: Doubleday, 1958) 5. See also Lorraine Helms,
"The High Roman Fashion: Sacrifice, Suicide and the Shakespearean
Stage," Publications of the Modern Language Association of America
107.3 (May, 1992).
-
-
Edwin Wilson and Alvin Goldfarb,
Living Theatre: A History (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1994) 68.
-
David R. Slavitt, preface, Seneca:
The Tragedies in two volumes, (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins U. Press,
1995). ix. See also Anna Lydia Motto, and John R. Clark, "Grotesquerie
Ancient and Modern: Seneca and Ted Hughes," Classical and Modern
Literature 5.1 (Fall 1984).
-
F.B. Watling, Introduction, Four
Tragedies and Octavia (London: Penguin, 1966) 19.
-
In the Greek myth, Tiresias' lack
of sight is punishment for viewing Athena while she bathed, but as a
dramatic function, Tiresias' blindness allows for Manto to describe
in great detail the sacrifice not only for the prophet, but for the
spectators. Many scholars maintain that Senecan tragedy was never staged
for an audience, due to difficulty of staging scenes such as this one,
and the danger of voicing certain political views therein (Watling 17).
If the plays were meant for reading or for recital at smaller gatherings,
Manto's detailed descriptions aid in visualizing the ritual.
-
Lucius Annaeus Seneca, Oedipus,
trans. E.F. Watling, Seneca: Four Tragedies and Seneca (London:
Penguin, 1966) 223.
-
See Sophocles, "Oedipus
the King," Sophocles I, trans. David Green (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press) 1991.
-
See Horace, Ars Poetica in
Roman Drama, ed. Robert W. Corrigan (New York: Dell, 1966).
-
Rebecca Weld Bushnell (quoting
Walter Benjamin), "Oracular Silence in Oedipus the King and Macbeth," Classical and Modern Literature 2.4 (Summer, 1982) 195.
-
-
-
Robin Lane Fox, Pagans and
Christians (San Francisco: Harper, 1986) 213.
-
R.M. Ogilvie, The Romans and
Their Gods in the Age of Augustus (New York: Norton, 1969) 67.
-
Arthur Stanley Pease, "M.
Tvlli Ciceronis de Divinatione," Illinois Studies in Language
and Literature 6.2 (May 1920) and 8.2 (May 1923) 95. The "models
of livers" refer to various Etruscan bronzes with arranged inscriptions
running over them.
-
Ogilvie 54. See also Polymnia
Athanassiadi, "Dreams, Theurgy and Freelance Divination: The Testimony
of Iambluchus," Journal of Roman Studies 83 (1993).
-
-
-
Pease notes that the examination
of entrails originally determined the fitness of the animal for ritual
sacrifice, and developed into a form of divination thereafter. Pease
offers four possible beliefs as reasons for the shift: "(1) That
the animal sacrificed was itself regarded as a deity, and therefore,
in its seat of intelligence, possessed of a knowledge of the future
[..]. (2) that the god entered into the perfect sacrificial exta where,
since he was voiceless, his will and foreknowledge had to be sought
by extispicine [...]. (3) that the god in accepting the sacrifice assimilates
the victim into his own being, as one assimilates food in eating it,
so that the victim's liver is brought into accord with the liver (and
hence with the foreknowledge) of the god himself [...]. (4) that just
before the moment of death the animal, like a human being becomes most
prophetic in power, so that changes take place at the moment immediately
before death" (Pease 97).
-
Marcus Tullius Cicero, The
Nature of the Gods, trans. Horace C.P. McGregor (London: Penguin,
1972).
-
The other category is worship
(Cicero 194).
-
-
ibid 188. Lucilius likewise
argues that divination is proof of divine power in the universe. Even
if the stories told by the diviners are fictions, he maintains, there
is enough evidence to show that the leaders of the people have benefited
from their advice on important decisions. "The state," he
says, "prospers only under the guidance of men of religious faith"
(128). Lucilius mourns the lost art of augury in the present, and pines
for the faith of their ancestors.
-
-
This view is echoed in Cicero's
de divinatione, as Cicero tackles the question of divination,
this time mediated by himself and his brother, Quintus, as the interlocutionary
characters. In a discussion of the practice of divination by entrails,
Cicero asks, "... I know what is indicated by a fissure in the
entrails of a victim, or by the appearance of the fibers; but what the
cause is that these appearances have meaning I know not" (Cicero,
"On Divination," On the Nature of the Gods, trans.
C.D. Yonge [London: Bell and Sons, 1902] 148-9) Pease interprets the
original Latin fissum in extis, quid fibra valeat as pertaining
to certain vital organs (spleen , stomach, reins, heart lungs, liver).
Fissa are stripes on the surface of the liver, a site of "mantic"
power, which in the case of sheep's livers were considered very significant
(Pease 95,96). Cf. the seven "veins" as described by
Manto on the liver of the bull.
-
Cicero, "On Divination," On the Nature of the Gods, trans. C.D. Yonge [London: Bell and
Sons, 1902] 193.
-
Lucius Annaeus Seneca, Naturales
quaestiones (3.32 ff), quoted in Thomas G. Rosenmeyer, Senecan
Drama and Stoic Cosmology (Berkeley: U of CA Press, 1989) 79.
-
Thomas G. Rosenmeyer, Senecan
Drama and Stoic Cosmology (Berkeley: U of CA Press, 1989) 79. Here,
Seneca's ambivalence echoes Cicero's statement the de divinatione that,
in the end, faulty human intervention will always guarantee the true
and complete messages of the gods will be deferred.
-
|